BOOK REVIEW
Paul Bains (2006). The primacy of semiosis: An ontology of relations. (Toronto
Studies in Semiotics and Communication) Toronto, Buffalo, London: University
of Toronto Press. 186 pp.; ISBN 10: 0-8020-9003-6, ISBN 13:978-0-8020-9003-4.
The conditions on the surface of a planet without living organisms are determined
entirely by the sunÕs energy and the laws of physics and chemistry, as James
Lovelock showed convincingly (Marg ulis, 1999). A planet with living organisms
deviates considerably from this scheme. The gas composi tion and temperature
will vary in a manner that cannot be predicted exclusively by the laws of physics
and chemistry alone. Such a planet contains incompatible gas mixtures and
temperatures whose relatively stable balance is actively co ntrolled by organisms.
The interaction between organisms and matter is one in which organisms
interpret and structure their abiotic environment according to biological princi-
ples. Parallel to this, the relationship to other organisms is a communicative one:
their mutual behavior underlies changeable semio tic rules of sign use with which
the biological individuals interact, i.e. coordinate and organize. The difference is
that organisms cannot develop such a ‘‘to follow or not follow’’-relationship with
natural laws, but underlie them in the strict sense.
From a biosemiotic perspective, there is an unbridgeable gap between on the
one hand chemical reactions (for example water molecules crystallizing to ice
when exposed to a certain temperature below zero) and on the other hand cell s of
a living organism receiving chemical molecules as signs sent from another part of
the organism to transport a vital message. Normally, message receiving, inter-
pretation and appropriate response generation involve species-specific interac-
tional rules. In contrast to the example of non-living matter (water ice), the
organismal semiotic processes may fail when (1) the message is generated
incompletely, (2) the message is somehow damaged or deformed during transport,
(3) the receiving entity is not appropriate, or (4) the interpretation by the receiver
is incorrect. All of these may lead to a response behavior incoherent with the
intent of the message.
In the last two decades the vocabulary in biology to describe all major and
minor arrangements and rearrangements of genetic and genomic content has
clearly turned to the use of linguistic and semiotic terms, e.g. ‘‘molecular prag-
matism’’ (Witzany, 1995), or ‘‘protein linguistics’’ (Gimona, 2006). In addition,
the description of interactions between cells and organis ms has turned to the use
of terms of communication theory, e.g. cellcell-communication, bacteria
communication, plant communication (Baluska et al., 2006).
Biological disciplines that work exclusively with a terminology of physics,
chemistry, mechanics, stochastics and formalizable mathematical sign systems
have difficulties making their languages compatible with linguistic, semiotic and
communicative vocabularies. Genetic and genomic contents, especially their
changing processes during evolutionary events, involve the complementary role of
combinatorial (syntactic), context-sensitive (pragmatic) and content-specific
(semantic) rules. Such rules apply not only to the genetic storage medium of DNA
but as our increasing knowledge of epigenetics has shown equally to the
Acta Biotheoretica (2006) 54:305311 Springer 2007
DOI: 10.1007/s10441-007-9004-y
concrete interactional context of the DNA-bearing organism. Parallel to this, the
descent, evolution and precision of signal-mediated coordination and cooperation
in single-cell populations such as populations of bacteria or protoctists and in
multicellular organisms like fungi, animals and plants, clearly demonstrate that
communication functions only if the signaling exchange and inter pretation is
coherent to species-specific shared rules. Therefore, biological disciplines be gin to
look to non-biological disciplines like linguistics (Searls, 2002), semantics
(Barbieri, 2001), biosemiotics (Kull, 2005), biohermeneutics (Markos, 2002), and
action-theoretical communication theory (Witzany, 2000).
Not only in the case of biosemiotics this leads to an increasing interest in the
foundations of sciences which focus on sign-use, language and communication.
The interest in a general theory of signs, i.e. semiotics, goes hand in hand with the
lack of a unique theory or methodology that can provide the foun dations of
semiotics. Realism, idealism, ontology, mathematical language theory, systems
and information theory, naturalism, semioticism, pragmaticism, structuralism
and constructivism are some of the many argumentative lines of (philosophical)
foundations, which compete in several semiotic subdisciplines such as in socio-,
cultural- or bio-semiotics.
Paul Bains undertakes an ambitious approach to work out an ontological
foundation not only of semiotics but of philosophy in general. This means
acknowledging sign processes (semioses) as real relations prior to any knowledge.
On this view, semioses and the relations constructed by them are at the very
foundations of Being and are prior to cognition and philosophy. Recurring to the
philosophies of Gilles Deleuze, John Deely, John Poin set and Humberto
Maturana, Bains looks at relations as being ‘externalÕ to their terms. Bains his-
torically reconstructs this line of thought, starting with the ontology of Aristotle,
the essentialism of scholastics and then proceeding further to Duns Scotus, John
Poinset, Charles San ders Peirce, Gilles Deleuze, Felix Guattari, Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz, Immanuel Kant, Humberto Maturana, Martin Heidegger,
Jakob von Uexku
¨
ll, John Deely, Alfred North Whitehead, Bruno Latour and
Isabelle Stengers. Bains suggests that understanding the ontology of relations
would allow us to develop a convincing representation of the action of signs. The
central assumption is that relations as relations are univocal in their ‘‘ad-esse’’.
This univocity is prior to thinking and Being, prior to the division of ens rationis
and ens reale. BainsÕs aim is to achieve a solution for the medieval nominalist
thesis, that it is possible in the example of the univocity of relations as relations to
show their objective Being.
Because external relations are the essence of Being, prior to thinking and
categorizing, they are also the precondition to our understanding and commu-
nication. We primarily recognize Being in the world as relations and, secondarily,
we can understand ourselves by understanding relations: ‘‘Univocal Being inheres
in language and ha ppens to things; it measures the internal relation of language
with the external relation of Being’’ (p. 7). The externality of relations to their
terms is essential also for Deleuze. The relations which we experience through
language and communication are prior to any language and communication
external Beings whi ch are focused by language. As ontological fundamentals,
relations are prior to language-derived constructions like idealism and realism.
Book Review306
This, so Bains, has its foundations in John Poinset and his reference to the
ontology of Duns Scotus and St. Thomas Aquinas. The relations exist objectively
(‘‘esse ad’’) and are intellectually (re)constructed. In contrast to objective Being,
Poinset constructs a not immanentl y given but ‘‘suprasubjective’’ level of being.
Not the theory is recognized as sign; rather, objective Being is recognized as a
pattern of univocal relations, which are physical relations in parallel. Bains finds
this univocal relationship realized in Jakob von Uexku
¨
llÕs Umweltlehre and his
pure relationships of species-specific ‘‘Umwelten’’. These relationships do not
describe the transition from a monadic subjective world to the outside world, but
are prior to this ‘‘suprasubjective’’. Bains compares this with the radical con-
structivism of Maturana and Varela and their concept of autopoiesis, which could
also generate univocal relations. But in the radical constructivism they propose,
the subject of knowledge would hide itself in a (closed) world of cognition.
Bains finds the processuality of relations in AristotleÕs substance-accidence
metaphysics and in the further developed processuality of Whitehead and
Maturana and Varela. But AristotleÕ s relations become independent of their terms
in OccamÕs nominalism (are the things in their terms or independent of them?).
Bains strives for a ‘‘realistic realism’’, as is the goal of Bruno Latour. Semiotically,
Bains seeks to reach the truth of relations in which we can speak abo ut the reality
of Being, which we recognize based on its stability in contrast to the experience
of an ongoing transformational world. As Bruno Latour (1990, 296) put it: ‘‘we
speak truthfully because the world itself is articulated.’’ Therefore, Bains is not
convinced coherent with Deely of KantÕs approach to mediate idealism and
realism, noumenon and phaenomenon.
Objective Being is (as Duns Scotus stated) a Being independent of cognition
and a subject of knowledge. One of the central questions is how to reflect upon the
relation between subject and object, inside world and outside world. Bains is
convinced that the semiotic reality is the real experience and cannot be reduced to
a thinking mind, whi ch generates a construction a posteriori, because it is pre-
categorical and univocal. The depiction of the material reality is univocal because
the semiosis represents a relation as it is in objective reality. The real relations are
signs by themselves and can be used to describe relations. This is a kind of self-
referentiality. Only with relations and therefore with semioses can someone
produce a univocity between signs and objective Being.
In a modern turn, the question arises as to how neurobiological processes c an
be combined with cognition and language. Biological organisms are self-referential
systems and con structed like ‘‘abstract machines’’. Cognition is therefore neither
an acquisition of knowledge nor an epiphenomenon of neuronal activity of the
brain, but rather an organisational activity of living systems: ‘‘Organization
implies a particular set of relations. For example, in an autopoietic system,
organization refers to the network of processes and relations that realize the sys-
tem. The ‘structureÕ of a living system is in constant transformation (whereas its
organization or abstract machine remains invariant). In a non-living system (such
as a toilet) the ‘organizationÕ consists in the assemblage of relations between an
apparatus capable of detecting the water level and another apparatus capable of
stopping the inflow of water.’’(p. 88) Maturana and Varela are more interested in
the process of relation than in the process of representation of signs. This brings
them close to speech act theory, because they place language in a social field of
Book Review 307
coordinating and consensual interactions. But they do not make the step from their
objectivistic perspective to participating inter actions: they adopt an observer
perspective because they think this is the appropriate perspective to take for
external observers of speech acts when trying to understand information. Because
of this Bains had an opportunity to turn his perspect ive into that of a participating
intersubjective one. Instead, he reduces social inter acting into the social-political
view of Nietzsche, Foucault and Deleuze: ‘‘languageing’’ and therefore
sign-mediated interactions are in any case a priori power relations, deformed and
non-reciprocal.
At this point it seems that we reach the most interesting part of the book. It
would be a crucia l step to transcend ontology towards a language-critical
reflection on the conditions for making valid ity claims with respect to scientific,
philosophical, etc. utterances. In the chapter ‘‘Autopoiesis and Languageing’’, for
example, the connection of the concepts of Maturana and Varela and Deleuze and
Guattari is brought in touch with formal conditions of speech act theory: to form
sentences and to initiate communication (i.e. rule-governed sign-mediated inter-
actions) are types of apriori and intersubjective social interactions. Deleuze and
Guattari integrate speech act theory radically: language and communication are
types of social interactions and not possible for solus ipse individuals. The
non-discursive immanent relations between utterances and actions as found in
illocutionary acts have three crucial consequences:
It is impossible to imagine language as a code, because a code is the
precondition of any explanation.
It is impossible to define syntax, semantics and even phonetics independently
of pragmatics.
It is impossible to maintain the distinction between language and speech.
But Bains doesnÕt reflect on a (pragmatic) relation of this approach to his own
utterances and their immanen t validity claims. The relation of sentences to their
validity conditions is not made, although this would have helped him to exit his
solus ipse subject of knowledge. Instead, he puts these positions of speech act
theory in perspect ive by reducing them to a social-political dimension of power
relations.
Bains acknowledges that the social dimension of language, as put forward by
Maturana and Varela and Deleuze and Guattari, is a non-reductive hypothesis.
At the same time he identifies this social dimension as a (onto-logical) biological
precondition. He re-naturalizes this social dimension of language into the
(objectivistic) observer-perspective of relations in interactions and the interacting
bodies (125). He even recognizes in Deleuze and Guattari the liberation of
solipsistic foundations. ‘‘The ‘subjectÕ becomes a symbiotic node within social
interactions’’ (127). This generates ‘‘se lf’’ as (a priori) part of socially interacting
entities, but at the same time reduces this liberating aspect to the non-critically
investigated post-structuralistic ‘‘exercise-of-power’’-metaphor. Bains cannot
imagine a reciprocal communication which gains its power by free agreements on
validity claims of utterances.
Bains wants to escape the monadology of the solipsistic subject of knowledge
of his ontologi cal approach by focusing on the relation as PoinsetÕs ad-esse
Book Review308
(‘‘being toward’’). He also subsumes the interacting subjects in this ‘‘being-
toward’’. As do Deleuze and Guattari, he identifies subjectivity interwoven in a
network of mental skills, situative ‘‘Umwelten’’ and social interconnectedness.
Based on his ontological point of view, however, he is unable to appropriately
respond to these typical questions on the relation between inside and outside,
thinking and world, terms (nouomenon) and reality (phenomenon). For him,
relations are primarily ‘‘external to their terms’’. This yields a semiotics of reality,
because the relations expressed in language are the relations of reality. Therefore,
Bains is convinced of the Primacy of Semiosis.
It is possible to think ontologically, to overlook the theory of science discourse
between 1920 and 1980 and its consequences (the linguistic turn and the pragmatic
turn), and to rebound the arguments to classical pre-Kantian metaphysics. But
this yields a hopeless entanglement in classical metaphysical problems of inside/
outside world, subject-object dichotomy, realism-objectivis m-idealism, language
and its ‘‘depiction’’ of ‘‘objective Being’’. The description of DeleuzeÕs speech act
reflections provided Bains with the only opportunity to escape the methodological
solipsist position that language and communication even the validity claims he
holds with his theoretical utterances are, as social interactions, intersubjective.
Then, he would have been able like the Wittgensteinian ‘‘Fly’’ to find his way
out of the glass of philosophy of consciousness and its unsolvable metaphysical
problem: how to make the move from a state of ‘‘private’’ consciousness to a state
of mutual agreement and cooperation.
In contrast to the results of recent speech act theory or to a modern
action-theory of sociology, Bains is unable to explain the commonly shared
understanding of utterances by at least two interacting subjects as being the
precondition of coordination and coop eration. But, if we want to understand
semioses (sign processes), we have to explain exactly this communal shared
understanding. BainsÕ approach therefore leads to an abstractive fallacy within
which the complementary roles of (a) the sign-using individual, (b) the significa-
tion and (c) the signified something is reduced to the relation ‘‘being-towards’’, the
signalling process without the signal-generating subject.
Moreover, the thesis that relations by themselves are univocal creates
problems. It would imply a strict relation between sentences, which express
relations to the reality. This attempt to construct a pure representational langu age
is doomed to failure because even a constructed formal artificial language does
not exclusively contain terms that are univocal. Scientific statements are not
attributable to immediate sensory experience, i.e., the language game used to
describe observations does not mirror the brain activity during the perception of
reality.
In the terms of BainsÕ language of ontology, problems also arise with under-
standing speech acts. ItÕs not the identification of the relation, which is established by
these acts, but the understanding of the rules which govern the activity. This means I
can also understand an act that runs counter to the rules. Speech acts I can under-
stand if I share rule-governed sign-mediated interactions with at least one other
subject. This has bee n shown by WittgensteinÕs private-language-argument in that
‘‘It is not possible that there should have been only one occasion on which someone
obeyed a rule.’’ (Wittgenstein, 1968: 80). The competence to follow (semiotic) rules
derived a priori from the experience of being part of social interactions. It is correct
Book Review 309
that interactions depend on real (or secondarily imagined) communal interactions,
i.e. relations, but relations are the result of interacting subjects.
Semiotics, linguistics as well as communication theory and action theory
share a present understanding of the primacy of pragmatics, as described by
Bains using the ‘‘languageing’’-concept of Deleuze. This would have been the
opportunity for Bains to leave behind the ontology approach and his (solus
ipse) observer perspective and to realize that his utterances combined
with his validity claims for the sentences he produces are part of a language
a priori; he is unable to transcend this a priori through an ontological
perspective. Every ontology in principle has to form sentences with validity
claims. But he relativizes this language-a priori through a (post-structuralist)
verdict that language per se is not ‘‘objective’’, but rather a tool of ‘‘power-
play’’ between communicative interactors.
The ontology of relations as an external-to-their-terms description of reality of
relation-being is not helpful in understanding what generates relations between
speech act subject s. Such an understanding must be coherent in both a scientific
description as well as in an everyday langua ge description to gain acceptance for
validity claims by those who interact. This includes (Witzany, 2006):
1) The simultaneous understanding of identical meanings in two interacting
partners, as expressed in successful coordination of actions;
2) The different iation be tween deep and superficial grammar of utterances along
with differentiation between locutionary, illocutionary and performative
speech acts;
3) The differentiation between communicative (reciprocal) interactions and
strategic (manipulative) interactions of communicating subjects;
4) The differences of the validity claims which are held with every utterance.
Such an understanding of language-use by humans has to become clear before
any meta physical or ontological utterance (neces sarily undertaken in a language).
Only such an understand ing enables critical reflection on the conditions which
must be fulfilled if a common agreement on validity claims is to be reached
between interactional partners. Or how could I mention an ontological thesis
without it having been expressed in an utterance by somebody?
REFERENCES
Margulis, L. (1999). Die andere Evolution. Heidelberg: Spektrum Akademischer Verlag.
Witzany, G. (1995). From the ‘Logic of Molecular SyntaxÕ to Molecular Pragmatism. Evolution and
Cognition 1(2): 148168.
Gimona, M. (2006). Protein linguistics a grammar for modular protein assembly?. Nature Reviews
7: 6873.
Baluska, F., S. Mancuso and D. Volkmann (2006). Communication in plants: Neuronal aspects
of plant life. Heidelberg/New York: Springer.
Searls, D.B. (2002). The language of genes. Nature 420: 211217.
Barbieri, M. (2001). The organic codes. The birth of semantic biology. Ancona: PeQuod.
Kull, K. (2005). A brief history of biosemiotics. Journal of Biosemiotics 1: 134.
Markos, A. (2002). Readers of the book of life. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.
Witzany, G. (2000). Life: The communicative structure. Norderstedt: Libri Books on Demand.
Book Review310
Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil & Blackwell.
Witzany, G. (2006). The Logos of the Bios 1. Contributions to the foundation of a three-leveled
biosemiotics. Helsinki: Umweb.
Guenther Witzany
telos Philosophische Praxis, Vogelsangstr 18c, A-5111, Buermoos/Salzburg,
Austria.
Book Review 311